Results for 'John T. Leahy'

1000+ found
Order:
  1.  37
    Embodied ethics: Some common concerns of religion and business. [REVIEW]John T. Leahy - 1986 - Journal of Business Ethics 5 (6):465 - 472.
    De George's understanding of theology is limited to one of five commonly recognized models of theology, the orthodox model. This model is vulnerable to De George's criticisms. When religious ethics operates out of the revisionist model of theology, however, his criticisms lose their sting. Revisionist religious ethics, moreover, can make a fruitful contribution to business ethics. Such a religious ethic acknowledges the embodiment dimension of business activities, it complements philosophical analysis with the practice of moral discernment, and it recognizes irony (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  2.  27
    Stable generic structures.John T. Baldwin & Niandong Shi - 1996 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 79 (1):1-35.
    Hrushovski originated the study of “flat” stable structures in constructing a new strongly minimal set and a stable 0-categorical pseudoplane. We exhibit a set of axioms which for collections of finite structure with dimension function δ give rise to stable generic models. In addition to the Hrushovski examples, this formalization includes Baldwin's almost strongly minimal non-Desarguesian projective plane and several others. We develop the new case where finite sets may have infinite closures with respect to the dimension function δ. In (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   37 citations  
  3.  16
    Model Theory and the Philosophy of Mathematical Practice: Formalization Without Foundationalism.John T. Baldwin - 2018 - Cambridge University Press.
    Major shifts in the field of model theory in the twentieth century have seen the development of new tools, methods, and motivations for mathematicians and philosophers. In this book, John T. Baldwin places the revolution in its historical context from the ancient Greeks to the last century, argues for local rather than global foundations for mathematics, and provides philosophical viewpoints on the importance of modern model theory for both understanding and undertaking mathematical practice. The volume also addresses the impact (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  4.  77
    Axiomatizing Changing Conceptions of the Geometric Continuum I: Euclid-Hilbert†.John T. Baldwin - 2018 - Philosophia Mathematica 26 (3):346-374.
    We give a general account of the goals of axiomatization, introducing a variant on Detlefsen’s notion of ‘complete descriptive axiomatization’. We describe how distinctions between the Greek and modern view of number, magnitude, and proportion impact the interpretation of Hilbert’s axiomatization of geometry. We argue, as did Hilbert, that Euclid’s propositions concerning polygons, area, and similar triangles are derivable from Hilbert’s first-order axioms. We argue that Hilbert’s axioms including continuity show much more than the geometrical propositions of Euclid’s theorems and (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  5.  19
    The Dividing Line Methodology: Model Theory Motivating Set Theory.John T. Baldwin - 2021 - Theoria 87 (2):361-393.
    We explore Shelah's model‐theoretic dividing line methodology. In particular, we discuss how problems in model theory motivated new techniques in model theory, for example classifying theories by their potential (consistently with Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC)) spectrum of cardinals in which there is a universal model. Two other examples are the study (with Malliaris) of the Keisler order leading to a new ZFC result on cardinal invariants and attempts to clarify the “main gap” by reducing the (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  6.  22
    As an abstract elementary class.John T. Baldwin, Paul C. Eklof & Jan Trlifaj - 2007 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 149 (1-3):25-39.
    In this paper we study abstract elementary classes of modules. We give several characterizations of when the class of modules A with is abstract elementary class with respect to the notion that M1 is a strong submodel M2 if the quotient remains in the given class.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   11 citations  
  7.  25
    The amalgamation spectrum.John T. Baldwin, Alexei Kolesnikov & Saharon Shelah - 2009 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 74 (3):914-928.
    We study when classes can have the disjoint amalgamation property for a proper initial segment of cardinals. Theorem A For every natural number k, there is a class $K_k $ defined by a sentence in $L_{\omega 1.\omega } $ that has no models of cardinality greater than $ \supset _{k - 1} $ , but $K_k $ has the disjoint amalgamation property on models of cardinality less than or equal to $\mathfrak{N}_{k - 3} $ and has models of cardinality $\mathfrak{N}_{k (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   8 citations  
  8.  72
    The stability spectrum for classes of atomic models.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2012 - Journal of Mathematical Logic 12 (1):1250001-.
    We prove two results on the stability spectrum for Lω1,ω. Here [Formula: see text] denotes an appropriate notion of Stone space of m-types over M. Theorem for unstable case: Suppose that for some positive integer m and for every α μ, K is not i-stable in μ. These results provide a new kind of sufficient condition for the unstable case and shed some light on the spectrum of strictly stable theories in this context. The methods avoid the use of compactness (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  9.  39
    Axiomatizing Changing Conceptions of the Geometric Continuum II: Archimedes-Descartes-Hilbert-Tarski†.John T. Baldwin - 2019 - Philosophia Mathematica 27 (1):33-60.
    In Part I of this paper we argued that the first-order systems HP5 and EG are modest complete descriptive axiomatization of most of Euclidean geometry. In this paper we discuss two further modest complete descriptive axiomatizations: Tarksi’s for Cartesian geometry and new systems for adding $$\pi$$. In contrast we find Hilbert’s full second-order system immodest for geometrical purposes but appropriate as a foundation for mathematical analysis.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  10.  91
    Constructing ω-stable structures: Rank 2 fields.John T. Baldwin & Kitty Holland - 2000 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 65 (1):371-391.
    We provide a general framework for studying the expansion of strongly minimal sets by adding additional relations in the style of Hrushovski. We introduce a notion of separation of quantifiers which is a condition on the class of expansions of finitely generated models for the expanded theory to have a countable ω-saturated model. We apply these results to construct for each sufficiently fast growing finite-to-one function μ from 'primitive extensions' to the natural numbers a theory T μ of an expansion (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  11.  23
    Model Companions of for Stable T.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2001 - Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 42 (3):129-142.
    We introduce the notion T does not omit obstructions. If a stable theory does not admit obstructions then it does not have the finite cover property (nfcp). For any theory T, form a new theory by adding a new unary function symbol and axioms asserting it is an automorphism. The main result of the paper asserts the following: If T is a stable theory, T does not admit obstructions if and only if has a model companion. The proof involves some (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  12.  37
    Constructing ω-stable structures: model completeness.John T. Baldwin & Kitty Holland - 2004 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 125 (1-3):159-172.
    The projective plane of Baldwin 695) is model complete in a language with additional constant symbols. The infinite rank bicolored field of Poizat 1339) is not model complete. The finite rank bicolored fields of Baldwin and Holland 371; Notre Dame J. Formal Logic , to appear) are model complete. More generally, the finite rank expansions of a strongly minimal set obtained by adding a ‘random’ unary predicate are almost strongly minimal and model complete provided the strongly minimal set is ‘well-behaved’ (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  13. Almost strongly minimal theories. I.John T. Baldwin - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (3):487-493.
  14.  15
    A Hanf number for saturation and omission: the superstable case.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2014 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 60 (6):437-443.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  15.  16
    Categoricity.John T. Baldwin - 2009 - American Mathematical Society.
    CHAPTER 1 Combinatorial Geometries and Infinitary Logics In this chapter we introduce two of the key concepts that are used throughout the text. ...
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  16.  9
    Social Neuroscience: People Thinking About Thinking People.John T. Cacioppo, Penny S. Visser & Cynthia L. Pickett (eds.) - 2006 - MIT Press.
    Studies in the neurobiological underpinnings of social information processing bypsychologists, neurobiologists, psychiatrists, radiologists, and neurologists, using methods thatrange from brain imaging techniques to comparative analyses.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  17.  24
    Stability theory and algebra.John T. Baldwin - 1979 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 44 (4):599-608.
  18.  42
    Examples of non-locality.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2008 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 73 (3):765-782.
    We use κ-free but not Whitehead Abelian groups to constructElementary Classes (AEC) which satisfy the amalgamation property but fail various conditions on the locality of Galois-types. We introduce the notion that an AEC admits intersections. We conclude that for AEC which admit intersections, the amalgamation property can have no positive effect on locality: there is a transformation of AEC's which preserves non-locality but takes any AEC which admits intersections to one with amalgamation. More specifically we have: Theorem 5.3. There is (...)
    Direct download (6 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  19.  29
    John W. Rosenthal. A new proof of a theorem of Shelah. The journal of symbolic logic, vol. 37 , pp. 133–134.John T. Baldwin - 1973 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 38 (4):649.
  20.  19
    Disjoint amalgamation in locally finite aec.John T. Baldwin, Martin Koerwien & Michael C. Laskowski - 2017 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 82 (1):98-119.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  21. A puzzle about laws, symmetries and measurability.John T. Roberts - 2008 - British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 59 (2):143-168.
    I describe a problem about the relations among symmetries, laws and measurable quantities. I explain why several ways of trying to solve it will not work, and I sketch a solution that might work. I discuss this problem in the context of Newtonian theories, but it also arises for many other physical theories. The problem is that there are two ways of defining the space-time symmetries of a physical theory: as its dynamical symmetries or as its empirical symmetries. The two (...)
    Direct download (14 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   34 citations  
  22.  34
    Diverse classes.John T. Baldwin - 1989 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 54 (3):875-893.
    Let $\mathbf{I}(\mu,K)$ denote the number of nonisomorphic models of power $\mu$ and $\mathbf{IE}(\mu,K)$ the number of nonmutually embeddable models. We define in this paper the notion of a diverse class and use it to prove a number of results. The major result is Theorem B: For any diverse class $K$ and $\mu$ greater than the cardinality of the language of $K$, $\mathbf{IE}(\mu,K) \geq \min(2^\mu,\beth_2).$ From it we deduce both an old result of Shelah, Theorem C: If $T$ is countable and (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  23.  48
    Transfering saturation, the finite cover property, and stability.John T. Baldwin, Rami Grossberg & Saharon Shelah - 1999 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (2):678-684.
    $\underline{\text{Saturation is} (\mu, \kappa)-\text{transferable in} T}$ if and only if there is an expansion T 1 of T with ∣ T 1 ∣ = ∣ T ∣ such that if M is a μ-saturated model of T 1 and ∣ M ∣ ≥ κ then the reduct M ∣ L(T) is κ-saturated. We characterize theories which are superstable without f.c.p., or without f.c.p. as, respectively those where saturation is (ℵ 0 , λ)- transferable or (κ (T), λ)-transferable for all λ. (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  24. Almost strongly minimal theories. II.John T. Baldwin - 1972 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 37 (4):657-660.
    Direct download (9 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  25. The Law Governed Universe.John T. Roberts - 2008 - New York: Oxford University Press.
    The law-governed world-picture -- A remarkable idea about the way the universe is cosmos and compulsion -- The laws as the cosmic order : the best-system approach -- The three ways : no-laws, non-governing-laws, governing-laws -- Work that laws do in science -- An important difference between the laws of nature and the cosmic order -- The picture in four theses -- The strategy of this book -- The meta-theoretic conception of laws -- The measurability approach to laws -- What (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   62 citations  
  26.  12
    Hanf numbers for extendibility and related phenomena.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 2022 - Archive for Mathematical Logic 61 (3):437-464.
    This paper contains portions of Baldwin’s talk at the Set Theory and Model Theory Conference and a detailed proof that in a suitable extension of ZFC, there is a complete sentence of \ that has maximal models in cardinals cofinal in the first measurable cardinal and, of course, never again.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  27.  35
    A model theoretic approach to malcev conditions.John T. Baldwin & Joel Berman - 1977 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 42 (2):277-288.
    A varietyV satisfies a strong Malcev condition ∃f1,…, ∃fnθ where θ is a conjunction of equations in the function variablesf1, …,fnand the individual variablesx1, …,xm, if there are polynomial symbolsp1, …,pnin the language ofVsuch that ∀x1, …,xmθ is a law ofV. Thus a strong Malcev condition involves restricted second order quantification of a strange sort. The quantification is restricted to functions which are “polynomially definable”. This notion was introduced by Malcev [6] who used it to describe those varieties all of (...)
    Direct download (8 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  53
    Some contributions to definability theory for languages with generalized quantifiers.John T. Baldwin & Douglas E. Miller - 1982 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 47 (3):572-586.
  29.  33
    Saharon Shelah. There are just four second-order quantifiers. Israel journal of mathematics, vol. 15 , pp. 282–300.John T. Baldwin - 1986 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 51 (1):234.
  30.  24
    Uncountable categoricity of local abstract elementary classes with amalgamation.John T. Baldwin & Olivier Lessmann - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 143 (1-3):29-42.
    We give a complete and elementary proof of the following upward categoricity theorem: let be a local abstract elementary class with amalgamation and joint embedding, arbitrarily large models, and countable Löwenheim–Skolem number. If is categorical in 1 then is categorical in every uncountable cardinal. In particular, this provides a new proof of the upward part of Morley’s theorem in first order logic without any use of prime models or heavy stability theoretic machinery.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  31.  6
    Upward categoricity of very tame abstract elementary classes with amalgamation.John T. Baldwin & Olivier Lessmann - 2006 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 143 (1-3):29-42.
  32.  16
    First-order theories of abstract dependence relations.John T. Baldwin - 1984 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 26 (3):215-243.
  33.  21
    Iterated elementary embeddings and the model theory of infinitary logic.John T. Baldwin & Paul B. Larson - 2016 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 167 (3):309-334.
  34.  32
    DOP and FCP in generic structures.John T. Baldwin & Saharon Shelah - 1998 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 63 (2):427-438.
  35. A mixed bag: Political change in central and eastern europe and its impact on philosophical thought.John T. Sanders - 1994 - In Dane R. Gordon (ed.), Philosophy in post-communist europe. Rodopi.
    The most important voices concerning the changes now occurring in Central and Eastem Europe are those that come from within, for those voices are informed not only by indifferent data and objective reports, but by personal hopes, fears, desires and needs. Without careful consideration of what such voices say, judgment can only be sterile. Furthermore, policy decisions made without the benefit of the intemal perspective are likely to be flawed, and ineffectual. Policies won’t work if they do not take into (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  36.  79
    The classical limit of quantum theory.John T. Bruer - 1982 - Synthese 50 (2):167 - 212.
    Both physicists and philosophers claim that quantum mechanics reduces to classical mechanics as 0, that classical mechanics is a limiting case of quantum mechanics. If so, several formal and non-formal conditions must be satisfied. These conditions are satisfied in a reduction using the Wigner transformation to map quantum mechanics onto the classical phase plane. This reduction does not, however, assist in providing an adequate metaphysical interpretation of quantum theory.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  37.  54
    CP-Law Statements as Vague, Self-Referential, Self-Locating, Statistical, and Perfectly in Order.John T. Roberts - 2014 - Erkenntnis 79 (S10):1775-1786.
    I propose understanding CP-law statements as statements that assert the existence of vague statistical laws, not by fully specifying the contents of those laws, but by picking them out via a description that is both self-referential and self-locating. I argue that this proposal validates many common assumptions about CP-laws and correctly classifies many examples of putative CP-laws. It does this while avoiding the most serious worries that motivate some philosophers to be skeptical of CP-laws, namely the worry that they lack (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   7 citations  
  38.  16
    Almost galois ω-stable classes.John T. Baldwin, Paul B. Larson & Saharon Shelah - 2015 - Journal of Symbolic Logic 80 (3):763-784.
  39.  46
    Completeness and categoricity (in power): Formalization without foundationalism.John T. Baldwin - 2014 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 20 (1):39-79.
    We propose a criterion to regard a property of a theory (in first or second order logic) as virtuous: the property must have significant mathematical consequences for the theory (or its models). We then rehearse results of Ajtai, Marek, Magidor, H. Friedman and Solovay to argue that for second order logic, ‘categoricity’ has little virtue. For first order logic, categoricity is trivial; but ‘categoricity in power’ has enormous structural consequences for any of the theories satisfying it. The stability hierarchy extends (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  40.  16
    Henkin constructions of models with size continuum.John T. Baldwin & Michael C. Laskowski - 2019 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 25 (1):1-33.
    We describe techniques for constructing models of size continuum inωsteps by simultaneously building a perfect set of enmeshed countable Henkin sets. Such models have perfect, asymptotically similar subsets. We survey applications involving Borel models, atomic models, two-cardinal transfers and models respecting various closure relations.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  41.  60
    K‐generic Projective Planes have Morley Rank Two or Infinity.John T. Baldwin & Masanori Itai - 1994 - Mathematical Logic Quarterly 40 (2):143-152.
    We show that K-generic projective planes have Morley rank either two or infinity. We also show give a direct argument that such planes are not Desarguesian.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  42.  9
    Education and Development in Latin America.John T. K. Adams & Laurence Gale - 1970 - British Journal of Educational Studies 18 (1):101.
    First published in 1969, this volume presents a survey of the contemporary national education system in Latin American countries. Laurence Gale describes the uneven provision of schools for different sections of the community and the problems which arise with the racial, cultural and geographical difficulties. He examines the main features in education throughout Latin America, areas of co-operation and agreement and differences of policy and provision.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43. An Ontology of Affordances.John T. Sanders - 1997 - Ecological Psychology 9 (1):97-112.
    I argue that the most promising approach to understanding J.J. Gibson's "affordances" takes affordances themselves as ontological primitives, instead of treating them as dispositional properties of more primitive things, events, surfaces, or substances. These latter are best treated as coalescences of affordances present in the environment (or "coalescences of use-potential," as in Sanders (1994) and Hilditch (1995)). On this view, even the ecological approach's stress on the complementary organism/environment pair is seen as expressing a particular affordance relation between the world (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   21 citations  
  44.  3
    Ernst Mach; his work, life, and influence.John T. Blackmore - 1972 - Berkeley,: University of California Press.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  45.  48
    Notes on quasiminimality and excellence.John T. Baldwin - 2004 - Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 10 (3):334-366.
    This paper ties together much of the model theory of the last 50 years. Shelah's attempts to generalize the Morley theorem beyond first order logic led to the notion of excellence, which is a key to the structure theory of uncountable models. The notion of Abstract Elementary Class arose naturally in attempting to prove the categoricity theorem for L ω 1 ,ω (Q). More recently, Zilber has attempted to identify canonical mathematical structures as those whose theory (in an appropriate logic) (...)
    Direct download (10 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  46.  20
    Trivial pursuit: Remarks on the main gap.John T. Baldwin & Leo Harrington - 1987 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 34 (3):209-230.
  47. Why the numbers should sometimes count.John T. Sanders - 1988 - Philosophy and Public Affairs 17 (1):3-14.
    John Taurek has argued that, where choices must be made between alternatives that affect different numbers of people, the numbers are not, by themselves, morally relevant. This is because we "must" take "losses-to" the persons into account (and these don't sum), but "must not" consider "losses-of" persons (because we must not treat persons like objects). I argue that the numbers are always ethically relevant, and that they may sometimes be the decisive consideration.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   15 citations  
  48.  8
    Ernst Mach's Graz (1864-1867): where much science and philosophy were developed.John T. Blackmore, Ryōichi Itagaki & Setsuko Tanaka (eds.) - 2010 - Enfield, NH: Enfield Publishing and Distribution Co..
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  49.  6
    Ernst Mach's influence spreads.John T. Blackmore, Ryōichi Itagaki & Setsuko Tanaka (eds.) - 2009 - Enfield, N.H.: Enfield Pub. and Distribution Co..
  50.  11
    Towards a finer classification of strongly minimal sets.John T. Baldwin & Viktor V. Verbovskiy - 2024 - Annals of Pure and Applied Logic 175 (2):103376.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
1 — 50 / 1000